Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-r5d9c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-07T22:19:31.843Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Appendices

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2022

Sharon Berry
Affiliation:
Ashoka University, India

Summary

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022
Appendices

An online appendix with further details is available at

www.cambridge.g.sjuku.top/PotentialistSetTheory

Appendix A Logico-Structural Potentialism

In this appendix I will fill in the formal details of the Potentialist translation strategy described in Section 6.4.

In Section A.2 I’ll define the core kind of structures (standard width initial segments of the hierarchy of sets) which my Potentialist set theory considers the possibility of extending. In Sections A.3 and A.4 and I will show how to cash out claims about it being possible to extend one initial segment V (and choice of some objects x , y , z within that V ) to a larger V containing an object w , without quantifying-in.

A.1 Functional Notation

To avoid overwhelming complexity, we will occasionally resort to functional notation. We now explain how to understand this notation in terms of the language of logical possibility described above.

Definition A.1 R is a function if (x)(y)(z)(R(x,y)R(x,z)y=z) .

So, for example, I would say that admiration is a function (in the actual world) if and only if no one admires two different people. For further notational convenience we will write f(x0,,xn)=y to abbreviate the claim f(x0,,xn,y) . When written informally we will understand f(x0,,xn) to stand in for some y such that f(x0,,xn,y) .

Finally, given two predicates D and R , I will say f is a function from D to R just if f is a function and (x)(D(x)(y)f(x,y))(xD(x))(y)(f(x,y)R(y)) and take the notions “surjective,” “injective,” “domain” and “range” to have their usual meaning.

A.2 Describing Standard-Width Initial Segments

So, let us begin by describing our intended initial segments. Recall the iterative hierarchy conception of sets from Chapter 2. Following Reference BoolosBoolos (1971) we imagined a hierarchy of sets consisting of a two sorted structure consisting of:

  • a well-ordered series of stages, with no last element; and

  • a collection of sets formed at these stages, such that a set is formed at a stage iff its members are all formed at earlier stages.

And we can say that something counts as a standard width initial segment if it satisfies all the requirements above except for the height requirement (that there is no last/highest stage).

I will define a formula V(set,ord,<,,@) in the language of logical possibility which expresses the fact that the objects satisfying “ ord ” are well-ordered by < (giving the well-ordered series of stages), the objects satisfying “ set ” act like sets under and that the relation @ relates sets to the stages at which they are formed, so that @(x,o) holds just if the members of x are all available at stages before o . Note that I will sometimes write the relations < and @ in infix notation, e.g., x<y rather than <(x,y) . Also, I will refer to the elements satisfying “ ord ” as ordinals and the elements satisfying “ set ” as sets.

Remember that here that I am using the terms “set,” “ord” and “ ” for mnemonic and readability purposes alone. As per the Putnamian strategy discussed in Chapter 2, my official Potentialist translation of set theory will employ only logical vocabulary and non-mathematical relations like “is a penciled point,” and “there is an arrow from … to … .”

Definition A.2 (Initial Segment). The tuple (set,ord,<,,@) forms an initial segment just if all of the following hold:

  1. 1. (ord,<) is a well-orderFootnote 1

  2. 2.

    (x)(y)[xyset(x)set(y)]
  3. 3.

    (x)(y)[@(x,y)set(x)ord(y)]
  4. 4.

    (x)(y)[x<yord(x)ord(y)]
  5. 5. (Fatness) For each o satisfying ord and each way of choosing some elements satisfying set from the sets (i.e., elements satisfying set ) available at stages o<o there is a set with exactly those elements as members:

    set,ord,<,,@(o)[ord(o)(x)P(x)set(x)((o)ord(o)o<o(x,o))(y)(set(y)@(y,o)(z)(P(z)zy))]
  6. 6. Every set is available at some ordinal level:

    (x)set(x)(o)ord(o)(x,o)
  7. 7. All sets available at some o such that ord(o) can only have elements which occur at some level below as elements:

    (x)(o)(x,o)(z)[zx(o)o<o(z,o)]
  8. 8. (Extensionality) No two distinct elements satisfying set have exactly the same elements:

    (x)(y)[set(x)set(y)x=y(z)(set(z)¬(zxzy)]
  9. 9. The ordinals are disjoint from the sets:

    (x)¬(ord(x)set(x)).

Note that we can think of Vα from the standard set-theoretic hierarchy as corresponding to an initial segment set,ord,<,,@ where ord,< has the same order type as α . Speaking loosely, this means if @(x,u) then x would be in V|u|+1 where |u| indicates the ordinal corresponding to u .

I will use V(Vi) to abbreviate the claim that seti,i etc. satisfy the sentence V(set,ord,<,@) defined above. I will also use V(x) to abbreviate ord(x)set(x) and V abbreviates ord,set,<,,@ .

A.3 Extensibility

Next, we need to cash out claims about one initial segment extending another.

Definition A.3 (Initial Segment Extension). Va extends Vb just if all the following hold:

  • V(Va)
  • V(Vb)
  • (x)[setb(x)seta(x)]
  • (x)(y)[setb(y)(xbyxay)]
  • (x)[ordb(x)orda(x)]
  • (x)(y)[ordb(y)(x<byx<ay)]
  • (x)(y)[ordb(y)(x@byx@ay)]

I will use VaVb to abbreviate the claim that Va (i.e., seta,orda,a,@a,a ) extends Vb (i.e., setb,ordb,b,@b,<b ).

If we followed Putnam and Hellman in quantifying-in to the of logical possibility, this would suffice to let us write Potentialist translations. We would translate the set theoretic utterance (x)(y)[¬x=y¬yx] as follows:

((x)V(V1)set1(x)V1(y)[V2V1set2(y)¬x=y¬y2x])

In words, it’s logically possible there is an initial segment (of the hierarchy of sets) V1 containing a set x (i.e., set1(x) ) such that its necessary, holding fixed V1 (i.e., set1,ord1,1,<1,@1 ), that any choice of an element y from a model of set theory V2 extending V1 must satisfy x=y¬y2x .

However, once we embrace the notion of conditional logical possibility, we can banish quantifying-in from our translations and thus avoid certain philosophical controversies.

A.4 Eliminating quantifying-in

The key “trick” which lets us eliminate quantifying-in from our Potentialist paraphrases, will be to supplement out initial segments Vi with a copy of the natural numbers (representing formal variables from the language of set theory) and an assignment function ρi which assigns each formal variable (i.e. natural number) to a set (objects satisfying seti) from Vi . Note that my only reason for using is that the natural numbers (under successor) contain infinitely many definable objects, which we can use to represent variables.

Specifically, we represent the natural numbers with the predicate and the function S and identify the formal variable xn with the natural number n (i.e., S(S(0)n ). Rather than use clunky formal variables xi everywhere we instead use normal letter variables x,y,z , etc. to stand in for particular formal variables and denote the number y stands in for by y , i.e., if y stands in for xn then y=n . We formalize this as follows.

Definition A.4 (Interpreted Initial Segment). Say that the relations in the pair (V,ρ) apply to an interpreted initial segment (written V(V,ρ) ) just if set,,ord,<,@ satisfy V(set,,ord,<,@) and ρ is a function from those objects satisfying to those satisfying set . More concretely, this amounts to the conjunction of the following three claims:

  • V(V)
  • ,S satisfy PA (the categorical description of the numbers given in Section J.3 of the online appendix)

  • ρ is a function from to set .

Note that we prove in Lemma J.11 in Section J.3 of the online appendix that it’s logically possible to have ,S satisfy PA .

I will often use the Va notation to denote the pair Va,ρa . And I will use Vn to abbreviate claims of the form setn,n,ordn,@n,n,ρn,,S (and similarly for Vn ). Note that we use the same relations ,S for every Vi .

We can now define a notion of extension for interpreted initial segment.

Definition A.5 (Interpreted Initial Segment Extension). The interpreted initial segment Vb extends Va while assigning x written VaxVb just if:

  • VaVb
  • v(Va)V(Vb)
  • (n(n))(ρa(n)=ρb(n)n=x)

1 See Definition E.2 in Section E of the online appendix for formal definition.

Appendix B Notation and Some Example Arguments

In this appendix I’ll prove some lemmas using only the basic inference rules in Chapter 3.Footnote 1 Most importantly, I’ll introduce a useful and intuitive way of reasoning about conditional logical possibility: inner arguments.

B.1 Inner Diamond

Let us start with the Inner Diamond lemma (Lemma B.1), which will help us capture natural reasoning about conditional logical possibility in a more intuitive manner. Specifically, while the Importing (Axiom 8.6) and Logical Closure (Axiom 8.7) axioms capture the intuition that we can deploy our normal tools of reasoning to infer what further facts must be true in some particular logically possible context, using them directly would force us to carry unwieldy long conjunctions of all facts we’ve derived are logically possible through our proofs. The Inner Diamond lemma justifies our use of more natural mathematical reasoning.

The intuition behind the Inner Diamond lemma is that reasoning like the following is valid:

Suppose we know the following. There are at least three cats. And it’s logically possible, given what cats there are, that every cat is sleeping on a distinct blanket. What else must be true in this logically possible scenario? We can “import” the fact that there are at least three cats (since any scenario which preserves the structural facts about how cathood applies must preserve this fact). So, by first-order logic, this possible scenario must be one in which there are at least three blankets. Thus, it is logically possible, given the facts about what cats there are, that there are at least three blankets.

Lemma B.1 (Inner Diamond). If Γ1Θ and Γ2,ΘΦ , where every element of Γ2 is a sentence content-restricted to , then Γ1,Γ2Φ .

Proof. Consider a scenario where the antecedent of the lemma is true. Assume that Γ1,Γ2 . Then we have LΘ by the first assumption. By successive applications Importing (Axiom 8.6) to each of the sentences Γ21,,Γ2n in Γ2 , we have L(ΘΓ21Γ2n) . Now by Logical Closure (Axiom 8.7) and the fact that Γ2,ΘΦ we can get LΦ . Thus Γ1,Γ2Φ , as desired. ■

We note that this lemma supports the following kind of reasoning (as illustrated in the above example).

We derive some sentence of the form Θ from the assumptions Γ1 . For instance, in the example above Θ would be the claim that “every cat slept on a distinct blanket” and would just be the predicate cat. We then wish to reason about the “world” whose possibility is guaranteed by the fact that Θ , e.g., the possible world which holds fixed (the structure of) the application of cat and at which every cat slept on a distinct blanket. In that world Θ (every cat slept on a distinct blanket) is true as is, intuitively, every fact content-restricted to cat true in the actual world. For instance, in the example above the fact that there are at least three cats is also true in that world (we refer to the act of taking a sentence content-restricted to and concluding it holds at the world whose logical possibility is asserted by Θ as importing). We then use proof rules to derive some desired conclusion Φ from Θ and the set of “imported” sentences Γ2 . For instance, in the above example, Φ is the sentence asserting there are at least three blankets. Intuitively, Φ must also be true in the logically possible world under consideration and thus Φ must be actually true. In the example above, Γ2 would just contain the sentence asserting that there are at least three cats. Since Θ,Γ2Φ and all sentences in Γ2 are content-restricted to cat this intuition is born out rigorously since the above lemma establishes that Γ1,Γ2Φ .

B.2 Natural Deduction with Inner Diamond Arguments

Since the process of entering contexts, i.e., using Inner Diamond (Lemma B.1) to reason about what else must be true in a particular logically possible scenario, is unfamiliar and can be a bit tricky, I will informally introduce a natural deduction system for the notion of proof defined in Chapter 8 together with some notational conventions which make it easier to keep track of arguments like the one above (especially in contexts where one must make multiple Inner Diamond arguments within one another).

This system is loosely based around that used by Reference GarsonGoldfarb (2003) and I follow his system in citing the line numbers justifying each inference rule to the left of the name of the inference rule, while indicating the assumptions a line depends on by placing those line numbers in brackets (line numbers not in brackets are the lines cited as immediate justification for the current inference). So, for example, we write down Φ 5,6X [2,4,5] on line 7 of a proof when rule X allows us to conclude Φ from lines 5,6 and the cumulative set of assumptions from which we’ve established Φ are the sentences on lines 2,4 and 5 . Note that this system satisfies the principle that if ψ appears on some line of the proof and Γ is the set of sentences appearing on the lines listed in brackets next to ψ then Γψ .

However, my system differs from Goldfarb’s in two primary ways. First, I will allow any purely first-order deduction to be compressed into a single FOL rule. However, I will still sometimes explicitly make use of  I to infer ϕ  ψ in cases where ψ can only be inferred from ϕ via modal reasoning. I will also use Ass. to indicate that a new assumption is being made.

Second, all modal axioms and axiom schema proposed in Chapter 8 are taken to be logical truths. So, any instance of these axiom schemata can be written down with no associated citations or assumptions. And, to save time, any instance of an axiom schema with the form ϕ  ψ may instead be regarded as an inference rule allowing us to infer ψ from ϕ (citing the line containing ϕ as a justification). For example, this is an acceptable deduction of P[(x)P(x)]  P(x) :

This is also an acceptable deduction of the same fact:

Third, and most distinctively, I will introduce a special context called a context (nestable to arbitrary depth) corresponding to reasoning via Inner Diamond (Proposition B.1), i.e., reasoning about what else must be true within some scenario which is known to be (conditionally) logically possible. I will graphically indicate what sentences are being asserted or assumed within this context by indentation and a sideways T labeled with a to indicate this context.

So, for example, we can represent the following extremely short Inner Diamond argument:

Given what cats and hunters there are, it’s logically possible that something is both a cat and a hunter. Any possible situation in which something is both a cat and a hunter, must be a situation in which something is either a cat or a hunter. Therefore, given what cats and hunters there are, its logically possible that something is either a cat or a hunter.

with a proof that looks like this:

The vertical line going from 2–3 above indicates those lines occur inside a special context. I call this a context to indicate that these lines contain reasoning about what must be true within a logically possible scenario in which (x)(cat(x)  hunter(x)) , while all the structural facts about, how cathood applies, are preserved.

What are the rules for writing things down in this context? Recall that the Inner Diamond (Proposition B.1) lemma says that if we have one conditional possibility claim (Θ) , and some facts Γ2 which are content-restricted to the relations being held fixed, then if we can show that any such possible scenario where Θ must also be one where Φ (by showing Θ,Γ2Φ ), we can infer the corresponding conditional logical possibility clam for Φ .

The key idea will be to use indentation and the Fitch-style sidewise T to graphically distinguish a main line of argument which goes from Γ2 (where the sentences Γ2 are content-restricted to ) and Θ and then Φ , from a supporting subproof which shows that Γ2,ΘΦ and thereby justifies the latter inference.

In the latter subproof (which I indent and mark off as a separate context) we are, in essence, attempting to milk new consequences from our knowledge that (Θ) , by thinking about what else must be true in a possible ( ) situation where Θ . Thus, I will call beginning such a subproof “entering the context” (associated with some claim (Θ) that was established on a previous line), and thereby beginning an Inner Diamond (Lemma B.1) argument.

One will only be permitted to import those claims Γ2 from the main line of argument (thereby assuming they continue to hold in the current context) which are content-restricted to the relevant list of relation . And we will only be allowed to close the Inner Diamond context, i.e., dropping back one level of indentation and writing down (Φ) , if we have proved that Φ holds inside the Inner Diamond context, by showing that it follows from the initial assumption that Θ and some facts Γ2 which we were allowed to import because they were content-restricted to .

Reasoning inside a context proceeds just as it does normally, with the exception that each line in the context must either be our initial assumption that Θ (where Θ is the sentence that opened the diamond context), an instance of “importing” (where the sentence must be imported from the parent context) or be deducible from previous lines within this exact context.

While the operation of In I is rather straightforward, I’ll call attention to one detail. Note that besides line 2 we wrote [2*] rather than [1] as one might expect. We do this to maintain the property that if Ψ is written on a line it is deducible from the lines written in brackets next to it.Footnote 2

One can leave the context above by going from knowledge that ϕ holds within this context to the conclusion that ϕ holds outside it. We indicate this inference pattern via the rule In E. This is the only way to introduce a sentence into the current context based on activity in a child context.Footnote 3

B.3 Example of Inner ◊ with Importing

We can also capture the reasoning in the slightly more complicated argument below, where we use knowledge of suitably content-restricted claims about the actual world to draw consequences from a modal claim.Footnote 4

It’s logically possible, given what cats there are, that each slept on a distinct blanket. There are at least three cats. Therefore, it’s logically possible, given what cats there are that there are at least three blankets:

B.4 Box Inference Rules

Although the is not an official item in our symbolism, but merely an abbreviation for ¬¬ , it is often helpful to reason in terms of it. Earlier we proved a couple of rules regarding inferences and here we present several more.

First, I present an introduction rule for .

Lemma B.2 ( I). If ΓΘ and every γΓ is a sentence content-restricted to then θ .

Proof. Suppose for contradiction that Γ,Θ are as above, but the lemma fails, i.e., ¬Θ . By Inner Diamond (Lemma B.1) with Θ1=¬Θ and Θ2=Θ , we can infer as Θ,¬ΘΘ¬Θ . Hence, by Elimination (Axiom 8.2) we can export the contradiction. Hence, Θ as desired. ■ Now I give the corresponding elimination rule.

Lemma B.3 ( Elimination). Θ  Θ .

Note that I prove a stronger version of this result in Section H of the online appendix that allows arbitrary substitution of relations when eliminating the box and, for ease of reading, I will also refer to that result as Elimination.

Proof. Assume the claim fails. We can derive contradiction immediately by applying Introduction (Axiom 8.1) to ¬Θ to derive ¬Θ , which is ¬Θ . We can write this in terms of the natural deduction system presented above as follows:

To give a more visceral sense of how proofs using this logical system work, see Section B.6 where I prove two lemmas which mirror results in set theory (which can be found in elementary texts like Reference JechJech (1978)).

B.5 ◊ Reducing and □ Expansion

Using first-order logic and the basic principles in Chapter 8 we can prove various useful lemmas.

The Reducing lemma (Lemma B.4) (together with    E) vindicates intuitive reasoning along the following lines. Suppose it’s logically possible, given the facts about friendship and enmity in the actual world, that something has a frenemy (i.e., there are items x and y such that x is the friend of y and x is the enemy of y ). Then it’s logically possible given (just) the facts about friendship in the actual world that something has a frenemy.

Lemma B.4 (Reducing). If then Θ  Θ ,

Proof. First note that if then any sentence of the form Θ is content-restricted to .

Assume that Θ . We have ΘΘ , by Introduction (Axiom 3.1). So, by Logical Closure (Axiom 3.7), we have ('Θ) . Then by Elimination (Axiom 3.2) we can conclude that Θ (since Θ is content-restricted to ). Thus, we have Θ  Θ . ■

We note that this immediately entails a corresponding expansion property for sentences under the .

Lemma B.5 (Box Expanding). If then Φ  Φ .

Proof. Assume that Φ and suppose for contradiction that ¬Φ , hence ¬Φ . By the Reducing lemma (Lemma B.4) we can infer ¬Φ , which contradicts our assumption that Φ . ■

B.6 Lemmas about Well-Orderings

To give a more visceral sense of how proofs using my logical system work, I’ll now prove two lemmas which mirror results in set theory (which can be found in elementary texts like Reference JechJech (1978)). In each case, I will make an argument verbally, and then follow it up with an argument using the formal notation (making explicit when we enter and leave Inner Diamond contexts).

Elsewhere I will present proofs in a more informal style. However, I hope the completely explicit proofs in this section will help the reader understand how these informal proofs can be expanded into a formal argument.

B.6.1 Reconstructing Well-Orderings: Part I

Jech’s version of the first lemma I am going to prove says the following:

“If (W,<) is a well-ordered set and f:W  W is an increasing function, then x<f(x) for each W .” (Reference JechJech 1978)

We can write a version of Jech’s Lemma follows (see Section E of the online appendix for the definition of a well-order):

Lemma B.6 If f is an embedding of the well-order W,< into itself then (x,y:W(x)  W(y))(x<f(x)) .

We define embedding as follows:

Definition B.1 (Definition of Embedding). A two-place relation f is an embedding of W,< into W,<' iff:

  • f is a function (remember we define what it takes for a relation to qualify as a function in Section A.1)

  • (x)[W(x)  (y)(W(y)f(x)] i.e., f maps all of W into W

  • (x)(y)(x)(y)[x<yf(x)<f(y)] , i.e., f respects < .

Remember that we’ve defined function so that the function f(x) is a convenient way of talking about the relation f(x,y) satisfying f(x,y)f(x,y)  x=x .

As usual, I will sometimes abbreviate the claim that x<yx=y as x  y .

Proof. To prove this, we will use essentially the same reasoning which Jech uses to prove his set theoretic version of this claim.

Assume that f is an embedding of (W,<) into itself, as per the statement of the lemma. And suppose, for contradiction, the lemma fails. As in Jech’s proof, our aim will be to use the properties of well-orderings to derive the existence of a < least counterexample, i.e., an x in W such that ¬x<f(x)  (y:y<x)(y<f(y)) and derive contradiction from this.

Applying Simple Comprehension (Axiom 8.4) to ¬x<f(x) tells us it would logical possible – while holding fixed the facts about how W,<,f apply in the situation we are currently considering – for the predicate G apply to just such counterexamples. That is:

W,<,f(x)(G(x)¬x<f(x))

Now we can enter this W,<,f context, i.e., begin an Inner Diamond (Lemma B.1) argument, where we reason about what else must be true in a possible scenario where (the facts about W,<,f in our original scenario are held fixed but) we also have:

(x)(G(x)¬x<f(x))

Now the premises of the lemma (that f is an embedding of (W,<) into itself and (W,<) a well-order) and the assumption that the conclusion of the lemma fails are all implicitly context restricted to W,<,f (seen by appropriately restricting all the quantifiers). So, all of these statements must all remain true in this new context and can by imported into this context.

Thus, we can infer that G is non-empty, from the assumption that the lemma fails, i.e., (xW(x))(¬x<f(x) , together with the fact that (x)(G(x)¬x<f(x)) .

We know that W,< is a well-ordering, and the least element condition from the definition of well-ordering (Definition E.2 in the online appendix) says the following:

W,<[(xW(x))G(x)  (yW(y)G(y))(zW(z)G(z))(yz))]

So, by Elimination (Lemma B.3) we can infer the existence of a least counterexample y , i.e.,

(yW(y)G(y))(zW(z)G(z)))(yz))

Now let z=f(y)<y . By our assumption that f is an embedding (and thus must respect < ) it follows from z<y that f(z)<f(y)=z . So, by the equation specifying the extension of G above we can infer that G(z) . Thus, z is an satisfies G(z) and is less than y . Contradiction .

Exiting the above context (i.e., completing our Inner Diamond argument), we get W,<,f . And from this follows by Elimination (Axiom 8.2) (remembering that is content-restricted to the empty list). Hence, the desired conclusion follows by contradiction. ■

Intuitively speaking, the argument above shows that the if there were a counterexample to the lemma then it would be logically possible (indeed logically possible, while holding fixed the W,<,f facts!) for the canonical contradiction to be true. But it’s not logically possible for to be true. So, there is no counterexample to the lemma.

Representing this proof in terms of our natural deduction system:

B.6.2 Reconstructing Well-Orderings: Part 2

Reference HorstenJech (1978) writes, “No well-ordered set is isomorphic

to an initial segment

of itself.” We can state the claim to be proved using the definition of isomorphism (Definition 7.4) from Chapter 7.

Lemma B.7 If (W,<) is a well-ordering and there is some x in W such that W applies to just those z<x in W then ¬W,W,<W,>fW',> .

Proof. Let W,W,< be as in the lemma and suppose for contradiction that W,W,<W,>fW',> . Using Inner Diamond (Lemma B.1) we can enter this context. We can import the fact W,< is a well-order (because it is content-restricted to W,W and < ). By first-order logic and unpacking definitions we can infer from the fact that f isomorphically maps W,> to W,> that f is an embedding of W,< into W,< . And, by the assumptions about W above, this implies that f is an embedding of W,< into ,< .

Now, to get contradiction, note that by Lemma B.6 (all instances of which are provable from empty premises, hence provable in any context) f does not map any object satisfying W strictly < -below itself. However, we know there is an object x satisfying W which is > all objects satisfying W and that W,>fW,> . It follows by first-order logic that f maps this x to some y<x . Thus, we have derived contradiction/the false ( ) from premises which would have to obtain in this (supposedly) logically possible scenario.

As before, we can conclude this inner W,W,< argument and returning to our original context with the conclusion that W,W,< . And from this follows by Elimination (Axiom 8.2).

This completes our proof by contradiction that there can be no f isomorphically mapping (W,>) to a proper initial segment of itself. ■

We can use the natural deduction system to expose the modal reasoning within this argument, as follows:

B.7 Pasting and Collapsing

Finally, I will conclude this chapter with two lemmas involving more complex modal reasoning using multiple contests. The first lemma tells us when two logically possible facts can be inferred to be jointly possible.

One cannot generally infer from Φ and to (ΦΨ) . Consider the case where Φ says there are exactly eight million things and Ψ says there are exactly nine million things. However, the Pasting lemma (Lemma B.8) says that one can make this inference in the special situation when the sentences Φ and Ψ are content-restricted so that they can only make claims about the objects satisfying some disjoint lists of relations and 𝒥 (and how these relate the actual -structure, which both Φ and Ψ preserve).

Lemma B.8 (Pasting). Let , 𝒥 and be pairwise disjoint sets of relations. If Φ , where Φ is content-restricted to , and Ψ , where Ψ is content-restricted to , , then (ΦΨ) .

Intuitively speaking, the facts about content-restriction above ensure that attempting to make the sentences inside both possibility claims true at the same time cannot impose conflicting demands. For the only relations whose extensions are relevant to the truth of both sentences are the relations on the list . And our assumptions say that it’s possible to make each interior sentence true while fixing the actual application of these relations.

Proof. Let Φ be content-restricted to , and Ψ to ,𝒥 , as per the antecedent:

Informally, this deduction corresponds to the following reasoning. Assume that Φ and Ψ. We can prove our claim by making two nested Inner Diamond (Lemma B.1) arguments.

First enter the ( ) context associated with Φ . That is, consider what else must be true in any such possible ( ) situation where Φ . In this situation Ψ must remain true, for it is content-restricted to , and we are considering a scenario which preserves the facts. By Ignoring (Axiom 8.3) it follows that ,Ψ .

Now enter this second, interior, , context. That is, consider what must be true in a further possible scenario where Ψ is true while all facts about how relations , applied in the scenario we previously considered are preserved. Here we clearly have Ψ . But we can import the fact that Φ from the previous context, because it is content-restricted to , . So we can deduce ΦΨ .

Now, leaving this inner , context, we can conclude that ,(ΦΨ) . And we can infer that that (ΦΨ) by Ignoring (Axiom 8.3) (because is clearly a sublist of , ).

So, leaving the larger context we can conclude that ((ΦΨ)) holds in the situation we were originally considering.

Finally, because (ΦΨ) is content-restricted to , we can use E to draw the desired conclusion (ΦΨ) . ■

The other lemma concerns when we can collapse multiple logical possibility operators into a single operator.

Lemma B.9 (Diamond Collapsing). If then ΦΦ .

Proof. To prove the left to right direction, suppose that 'Φ . Enter the context. In this context we have 'Φ . Since , by Reducing (Lemma B.4) we can infer Φ . Exiting the context, we have (Φ) in our original contest. So, we can apply Elimination (Axiom 8.2) to infer Φ .

To prove the other direction, suppose that Φ . Entering this diamond context, we have Φ and can infer that 'Φ by Introduction (Axiom 8.1). So, completing our Inner Diamond argument gives us 'Φ .

We also observe that there is a corresponding version of the above lemma.

Lemma B.10 (Box Collapsing). If then ΦΦ .

Proof. Note that this is equivalent to proving

¬Φ¬Φ

which is just

¬Φ'¬Φ

This is true by Diamond Collapsing (Lemma B.9). ■

1 Before beginning, let me note a technical point about how I will talk about lemmas. Consider the trivial lemma whose content is (x)R(x)  (x)R(x) . We don’t regard the proof of this lemma as merely establishing the fact that for some particular relation, e.g., redness, if there is some red thing then there is some red thing. Rather, we regard the lemma as standing in for the fact that this result is provable for any one-place relation or, alternately, as proving that the claim in the lemma is logically necessary.

Indeed, we will see shortly if we can prove (x)R(x)  (x)R(x) without any premises we can infer [(x)R(x)  (x)R(x)] and then (as we will also see below) substitute the relations under the and then eliminate it.

Thus, we allow deducing the fact that (x)G(x)  (x)G(x) from the trivial lemma asserting that (x)R(x)  (x)R(x) . This resembles the situation in first-order logic where we prove that substitution of bound variables preserves truth-value, and then don’t pay much attention to the particular bound variables used to express results.

2 To this end we treat the initial line in each context and every line introduced via importing (see below) as if they were assumptions inside that context. However, we mark these assumptions with an asterisk since they are justified assumptions (it’s safe to assume they are true in the context) and must be replaced with the line numbers from the parent context when we leave the context.

In accordance with this idea, a sentence ρ can be written down inside the “ context” governed by the claim that , iff:

  • ρ=Θ

  • ρ=Ψ for some Γ which is content-restricted to and occurs on an earlier line in the proof which is in the same context as the Θ statement used to introduce this Inner Diamond context. (I will, as usual, sometimes elide the steps needed to transform implicitly content-restricted sentences into first-order logically equivalent explicitly content-restricted sentences.)

  • ρ follows from previous lines within this context by one of the axioms or inference rules for reasoning about logical possibility presented in this book.

3 Note that In E may not be applied to any line with uncancelled (unstarred) assumptions introduced in the context being closed. Moreover, In E must take each starred line number j* on the line on which Φ appears (here that’s line 3 and Φ is (x)(cat(x)hunter(x)) ) and replace it with the assumptions of the line (in the current context) used to justify line j . For instance, in the current case the only (starred) assumption for line 3 is line 2. Looking at line 2 we see that it is justified by reference to line 1 (which is in the current context). So we copy the line numbers in brackets on line 1 into the brackets on line 4 (in this case that’s just 1).

4 Note that the sentence on line 2 “There are at least three cats” is content-restricted to {cats} (assuming that this abbreviates an FOL statement in the usual Fregian fashion). This fact allows us to import it into our reasoning about what the possible scenario where each cat slept on a different blanket must be like on line 4.

Also note that on line 5 we have proved “there are at least three blankets” with only assumptions [3*,4*] (which are starred because they were introduced by Inner Diamond introduction or importing). Thus, we have shown that the conclusion that there are at least three cats follows from things we are entitled to assume about any logically possible scenario witnessing the truth of the sentence on line 1. So we can apply In Elimination to complete our Inner Diamond argument, and conclude that cat (There are at least three blankets).

Finally, note that the assumption line numbers listed for our conclusion are [1,2] . For these are the assumptions needed for the claims about the actual world (namely the sentences on lines 1 and 2), which entitle us to assume that the possible scenario considered on lines 3–5 satisfy the assumptions on lines 3 and 4 , which imply there are more than three blankets.

See Appendix G in the online appendix for an explicit formal statement of this natural deduction system, and a demonstration that proofs in it obey the notion of provability above.

Appendix C Vindication of FOL Inference in Set Theory

In Chapter 9 I show that Potentialist translations of all the ZFC axioms are true and can be justified within my formal system. However, this is not enough to justify ordinary mathematical practice. We also need to show that everything set theorists derive from the ZFC axioms using FOL has a true and justified Potentialist translation. And this fact is not immediately guaranteed by the soundness of first-order logic, because our Potentialist translations of set theoretic sentences have a different logical form from the originals.

In this appendix I will show that, for any two sentences of Actualist set theory, if ϕ first-order logically implies that ψ then t(ϕ) implies t(ψ) . Specifically, I will show that, for every first-order logical proof in the language of set theory, there is a corresponding proof from my inference rules for logical possibility which takes us from the translation of the premises for this argument to the translation of its conclusion. That is, I will prove Theorem 9.1 from Chapter 9, which I restate below.

Theorem 9.1 (Logical Closure of Translation). Suppose Φ,Ψ are sentences in the language of set theory and ΦFOLΨ then t(Φ)t(Ψ)

Or, equivalently, if FOLΦ  Ψ then t(Φ)  t(Ψ) .

C.1 Proof Strategy

I will prove the above result by first establishing a more general result about Potentialist translations of arbitrary set theoretic formulae (below), which implies the fact we want about sentences. Note that any formula we are translating should be assumed to be in the language of set theory.

Proposition C.1. Given a set Γ of formulas in the language of set theory if ΓFOLθ then V(Vn),tn(Γ)tn(θ) , where tn(Γ) denotes the pointwise image of Γ under tn .

Remember that tn(Φ) intuitively represents the translation of Φ with respect to the structure Vn and the assignment function ρn . Thus, this theorem can be thought of as showing that first-order inferences are valid even with respect to the partial translation tn .

As one might expect, this more general result implies the Logical Closure of Translation, as we prove below.

Proof. Consider any Φ,Ψ such that FOLΦ  Ψ . It follows that ΦFOLΨ and by the theorem above, we know that V(Vn),tn(Φ)tn(Ψ) and thus V(Vn)  (tn(Φ)  tn(Ψ)) .

Now assume that t(Φ) . By this is just (V(V0)  t0(Φ)) . From this we may infer V(V0)  t0(Φ) and by using the fact that V(V0)  (t0(Φ)  t0(Ψ)) we can conclude V(V0)  t0(Ψ) . So we have t(ϕ)V(V0)  t0(Ψ) .

Since V(V0)  (t0(Φ)  t0(Ψ)) is provable from empty premises we also have t(Φ)V(V0)t0(Ψ) . So by Introduction (Lemma B.2) and the fact that t(Φ) is content-restricted to the empty sentence, we can infer t(Φ)(V(V0)  t0(Ψ)) . Hence t(Φ)t(Ψ) and thus t(Φ)  t(Ψ) . ■

We now prove Proposition C.1 via structural induction on first-order proofs (note that technically this is a meta-theorem and the induction occurs in our meta-language). However, first we need a formal definition of an FOL proof.

The choice to explicitly define a notion of proof (as opposed to simply defining the set of provable sentences) might seem odd here. After all, it would be mathematically more elegant to simply define provability as the smallest relation closed under certain rules. However, defining an explicit notion of proof allows us to induct on proof length in establishing the above proposition rather than trying to define some kind of well-founded relation on sequents.

We think of proofs in terms of the familiar tree structure, but formalize this notion in a way which makes it clear what rule is being applied at each point, as below.

Definition C.1 (First-order Proof). ΓFOLθ just if there is a first-order proof of θ from Γ=γ1,γm where this is inductively defined as follows (taking the various rule names are understood to refer to distinct constantsFootnote 1) and to denote an ordered tuple.)

  • If θΓ then Ass,θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=ϕψ and Pϕ is a proof of ϕ from Γ and Pψ is a proof of ψ from Γ then I,Pϕ,Pψ,ϕψ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=ϕ or θ=ψ and Pϕψ is a proof of ϕψ from Γ then E,Pϕψ,θ is a proof of θ from Γ

  • If θ=ϕψ and P is a proof of ϕ from Γ or ψ from Γ then I,P,ϕψ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If Pϕψ is a proof of ϕψ from Γ and Pϕθ is a proof of θ from Γ,ϕ and Pψθ is a proof of θ from Γ,ψ , then E,Pϕψ,Pϕθ,Pψθ,θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=ϕ  ψ and Pψ is a proof of ψ from Γϕ then   I,Pψ,ϕ  ψ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If Pϕ  θ is a proof of ϕ  θ from Γ and Pϕ is a proof of ϕ from Γ then   E,Pϕ  θ,Pϕ,θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=¬ϕ and Pψ is a proof of ψ from Γ,ϕ and P¬ψ is a proof of ¬ψ from Γ,ψ then ¬I,Pψ,P¬ψ,¬ϕ is a proof of ¬ϕ from Γ .

  • If P¬¬θ is a proof of ¬¬θ from Γ then DNE,P¬¬θθ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=(v)ϕ and Pϕ is a proof of ϕ from some ΓΓ with v not free in any member of Γ then I,Pϕ,(v)ϕ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=ϕ(v|v) where v’ is free for v in θ Footnote 2 and P(v)ϕ is a proof of (v)ϕ from some Γ then E,P(v)ϕ,θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ=v=v , where v is any variable then (=I),θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If θ is obtained from ϕ by replacing zero or more occurrences of v1 with v2 , provided that no bound variables are replaced, and all substituted occurrences of v2 are free and P=  is a proof of v1=v2 from Γ and Pϕ is a proof of ϕ from Γ then (=E),P=,Pϕ,θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

  • If Pψ¬ψ is a proof of ψ¬ψ from Γ then I,Pψ¬ψ, is a proof of from Γ .

  • ( E) If θ=¬ϕ and P is a proof of from Γ then I,P,θ is a proof of θ from Γ .

Note that there is no conflict between our definition of x as an abbreviation of ¬x¬ and our use of the introduction and elimination rules for rather than in proofs (the rule E simply applies to statements of the form ¬v¬ψ ).

Definition C.2 If P is a first-order proof then P is a subproof of P just if either:

  • P has the form R,P0,θ and P=P0 or P is a subproof of P0

  • P has the form R,P0,P1,θ and P is P0 or P1 or a subproof of P0 or P1 .

C.2 Proof of Main Result

We are now in a position to prove Proposition C.1.

Proof. Suppose that Vn is an interpreted initial segment, tn(γ) holds for all γΓ and P is a proof of θ from Γ . Furthermore, assume, by way of induction, that the proposition holds for all P a subproof of P . We prove that tn(θ) also holds (which by the inductive hypothesis demonstrates that V(Vn),tn(Γ)tn(θ) ).

Now consider the possible cases for P :

P=Ass,θ

In this case we have θΓ so we immediately have V(Vn),tn[Γ]tn(θ) :

P=R, where RI,E,I,E,  I,  E,¬I,DNE

This follows immediately from the fact that tn commutes with truth-functional operations and the validity of the above rules in our system for reasoning about logical possibility. For example, if I,Pϕ,Pψ,ϕψ where θ=ϕψ then tn(ϕψ) would be tn(ϕ)tn(ψ) and by the inductive assumption applied to Pϕ,Pψ we know that tn(ϕ) and tn(ψ) both hold, yielding the desired conclusion:

P=(=I),θ

In this case tn(θ) is ρn(v)=ρn(v) , which trivially follows from the assumption that Vn is an interpreted initial segment (hence ρn is functional with v in its domain):

P=(=E),P=,Pϕ,θ

By applying the inductive hypothesis to P= we have tn(v1=v2) , which is ρn(v1)=ρn(v2) . By the inductive hypothesis applied to Pϕ we can infer tn(ϕ) . As θ is obtained from ϕ by replacing zero or more occurrences of v1 with some v2 (where no bound variables are replaced and all substituted occurrences of v2 are free) the Variable Swap lemma (Lemma L.5 in Section L.2 of the online appendix) lets us deduce tn(θ) .

The proof of the Variable Swap lemma (Lemma L.5) can be found in Section L.2 of the online appendix but it should be intuitively clear that if ρn(v1)=ρn(v2) then replacing some number of occurrences of v1 in θ with v2 can’t change its truth-value:

P=I,Pϕ,θ

By our definition of First-order Proof (Definition C.1) θ=(v)ϕ(v) for some formula ϕ and variable v , and Pϕ is a proof of ϕ from some ΓΓ containing no formula γ in which v appears free.

If γΓ then by the inductive hypothesis applied to Γ , Pϕ and n+1 we have V(Vn),tn[Γ]tn(γ) . Now suppose Vn+1vVn . As v is not free in γ , by the Translation theorem we can prove that tn+1(γ) . Thus V(Vn),tn[Γ]Vn+1vVntn+1(ϕ) .

The Translation theorem (Theorem L.1) is provedFootnote 3 in Section L.2 of the online appendix. However, it intuitively says that the truth-value of tn(γ) only depends on how Vn assigns the free variables in γ and not on the height of Vn . Thus, if VmvVn and v isn’t free in γ then we can infer tm(γ) from tn(γ) .

As, by Lemma 7.1, every member tn[Γ] is content-restricted to Vn . Thus, by Introduction (Lemma B.2) we may deduce that

tn((v)ϕ(v))defVnVn+1vVn  tn+1(ϕ)
P=E,Pvϕ,θ

By definition of First-order Proof (Definition C.1), θ is equal to ϕ(v|v) for some formula ϕ and variable v where none of the substituted instances of v are bound and Pvϕ is a proof of vϕ .

To prove this claim we merely need to show that if every logically possible way of extending Vn with Vn+1 and choosing v makes tn+1(ϕ) true then whatever assignment Vn makes for v makes tn(ϕ(v|v)) true. To this end we must use the intuitive fact that whatever assignment Vn makes for v there is some extension Vn+1 which makes the same assignment for v . This fact is proved in the Pointwise Interpretation Tweaking lemma (Lemma L.1 in Section L of the online appendix).

We first note that by Pointwise Interpretation Tweaking lemma we have

Vn(Vn+1vVnρn+1(v)=ρn(v))

Enter this Vn context. By Lemma 7.1 each sentence in tn[Γ] can be inferred to remain true in this context.Footnote 4 So, by the inductive hypothesis applied to Pvϕ we may infer

tn((v)ϕ(v))defVn(Vn+1vVntn+1(ϕ))

Application of Elimination (Lemma 7.4) allows us to infer tn+1(ϕ) and from there, as ρn+1(v)=ρn(v)=ρn+1(v) we may apply the Variable Swap lemma (lemma Lemma L.5 in Section L.2 of the online appendix) to derive tn+1(θ) .

As θ=ϕ(v|v) if v isn’t v then v doesn’t appear free in θ . If v is v then ρn+1(v)=ρn(v) and in either case as Vn+1vVn we have that ρn+1 and ρn agree on all free variables in θ . Hence by the Translation theorem (Theorem L.1 in the online appendix) we can infer tn(θ) . Leaving the Vn context we have Vntn(θ) . Since by Lemma 2.1 tn(θ) is content-restricted to Vn by Elimination (Axiom 8.2) we can conclude tn(θ) .■

C.3 Justifying Truth Condition Adequacy

I claim that if our Platonist paraphrase satisfies the Definable Supervenience Condition and captures intended truth conditions for all sentences in S then the if-thenist paraphrase strategy above does as well. That is, we can produce a nominalistic sentence which is true at all the same possible worlds where the Platonist would say their logically regimented sentence is true – exactly the possible worlds where we think the English sentence being regimented is intuitively true:

Paraphrase: N(D  ΦP) is true at a world w iff the Platonist would say Φp . For suppose that the above conditions are satisfied for some applied mathematical sentence Φ and N, and D and P. I claim that Platonist must admit that if Φ is true iff N(D  Φ) For, consider any metaphysically possible world w. The Platonist thinks D is true at w, by the fact that they take D to be metaphysically necessary. But then, by the following theorem we have Φ iff my translation of Φ (i.e., N(D  Φ) ) is true.

C.3.1 Formal Justification for Truth Conditions Adequacy

Theorem C.1 Suppose that:

  1. 1.

    PN=
  2. 2. both Φp and D are content-restrictedFootnote 5 to PN

  3. 3. D is a categorical description of P over N ,

then[D  (ΦT(ϕ))]

.

Remember that T(ϕ)=N(D  ϕ) .

Note that while all theorems proved in this book hold with necessity, we make the necessity claim explicit here as it is used to justify claim that T(ϕ) matches the truth-value the Platonist intended ϕ to have at every metaphysically possible world.

Proof. Note that it is enough to prove D  (ΦT(ϕ)) as we may then invoke Introduction (Lemma B.2) to infer the necessity of the claim. So we suppose that D holds and verify ΦT(ϕ) .

( ) Suppose T(ϕ)=N(D  Φ) . By Elimination (Lemma B.3) we may infer D  Φ and thus Φ .

(    ) Suppose, for a contradiction, that Φ holds but T(ϕ) fails to hold. Thus, we can infer, N(D¬Φ) . Letting P be a set of new relations of the same arity as P and applying Relabeling (Axiom 8.5) we may infer N(D[P/P]¬Φ[P/P]) (where P/P indicates simultaneously replacing the relations in P by those in P ).

Now since we are assuming that both D and Φ hold we may infer N(DΦ) via Introduction (Axiom 8.1). As D and Φ are both content-restricted to NP (and thus D[P/P]¬Φ[P/P] is content-restricted to NP ) we may use Pasting (Lemma B.7) to infer

NDD[P/P]Φ¬Φ[P/P]

Enter this N context and import the following fact (content-restricted to the empty set) from the definition of categorical over (Definition 12.3): (D[N1,,Nm,P1,,Pn]D[N1,,Nm,P1/P1,,Pn/Pn]NPNP) Elimination (Lemma H.4 of Section H of the online appendix) we can infer DD[P/P]  NPNP and thus NPNP . Hence, we can use the Isomorphism theorem (Theorem I.1 of Section I of the online appendix) to infer from this and the fact that Φ holds that Φ[P/P] holds. But this contradicts the fact that ¬Φ[P/P] . Exporting this contradiction gives us the desired conclusion. ■

1 For instance, numbers if formalized in an arithmetic meta-language.

2 That is, if substituting v with v does not lead to any variable which was antecedently free becoming bound. Here θ(v|v) stands for the result of substituting all free instances of v in θ with instances of v .

3 Note that Hellman proves something analogous to this lemma in Reference HellmanHellman (1996), assuming there are infinitely many inaccessibles (but I make no such assumption).

4 Strictly speaking we only need to import the finitely many γΓ used to prove vϕ .

5 Intuitively, given any D that is a categorical description of P over N it should be possible to find a D' that imposes the same restrictions but is content-restricted to PN . However, it is not clear how to go about proving this.

Appendix D Archimedean and Rich Instantiation

It is easy to show that the platonic structures appealed to here (the natural numbers and the functions from the natural numbers to paths) definably supervene on the how nominalistic relations apply, via the techniques used in Section 12.2):

Platonistx has length a finite multiple of y”: for all n there are paths ci,1in with c0=x , c1=y and cix=ci+1 .

Then we can prove the uniqueness Putnam claims under the following nominalistically stateable assumptions, which mayFootnote 1 imply that space is infinite in extent:

  • given a path x there are paths y with length equal to any finite multipleFootnote 2 of x ;

  • no path is infinite in length with respect to another, i.e., if xLy then some finite multiple of x is longerFootnote 3 than y ;

  • the relations L,L have the basic properties you would expect from their role as length comparisons.Footnote 4

That is, the assumptions above imply that there is a unique (up to multiplicative constant) length function (from paths to the real numbers) respecting L,L . Hence there’s a unique length ratio function lr(p1,p2)=r such that for all functions f satisfying the above constraints, f(p1)/f(p2)=r .

One can also (as seems more in the spirit of Putnam’s cryptic remark about how his uniqueness claim is to be proved) establish the same uniqueness on the assumption that space is (roughly) infinitely divisible rather than infinite in extent, replacing the finite multiple condition by a finite division condition, i.e., for each path y and finite multiple m there is a path x such that m copies of x have the same length as y . And we can write a corresponding division rather than multiplication-based version of the Archimedean principle. Philosophers who have a more classical view of space might find such a condition more plausible as a necessary constraint on the nature of space (we will also consider the possibility that neither seems necessary below as well):

  • given a path x there are paths y with length equal to any finite multiple of x ;

  • no path is infinite in length with respect to another, i.e., if xLy then x is longer than some finite divisorFootnote 5 of y ;

  • the relations L,L have the basic properties you would expect from their role as length comparisons.Footnote 6

Standard measurement theoretic uniqueness arguments then show that if either of these two claims are satisfied then “length is richly instantiated” in the following sense:

L,L,path[D If f and g are functions satisfying Putnam’s measurement theoretic axioms for being a length function, then f and g agree up to a constant]Footnote 7

So, we know that if length is richly instantiated in a world w then we have uniqueness and the Platonist paraphrase above yields the correct truth conditions at that world.

D.1 Inferential Role Adequacy

We can also show that the nominalistic paraphrase strategy produced by our translation T preserves the desired inferential role of scientific sentences in S, capturing both inferences between scientific sentences and inferences between scientific sentences and observational sentences (on the plausible assumption that the latter can be understand as content restricted to some nominalist vocabulary).

It is easy to see that applying our translation T preserves inference relations between scientific statements in the following sense.

Theorem D.1 Suppose that Φ,Ψ are content restricted to P  N and ΦΨ then T(Φ)T(Ψ) . Furthermore, if T(Φ)T(Ψ) then (DΦ)Ψ .

Proof. As ΦΨ , we have (DΦ)(DΨ) by FOL. Suppose N(DΦ) , then by the above fact and Box Closure (Lemma H.2 of Section H of the online appendix) we have N(DΨ) .

Furthermore, suppose that DΦ . Above we proved that D(ΦT(Φ)) holds for all sentences content restricted to P  N . Thus, we can infer T(Φ) and T(Ψ) , so Ψ . Thus, (DΦ)Ψ . ■

Note the “furthermore” ensures that this translation strategy doesn’t let you prove any more than the Platonist thinks the scientist can prove.

We can also show the following theorem:

Theorem D.2 Suppose that the conditions for T being defined above are satisfied (specifically ND , i.e., the Platonist isn’t supposing the existence of incoherent objects), and that Φ is content restricted to N then ΦT(Φ) .

Proof. ( ) Assume Φ . Hence, we may infer DΦ . As this proof only assumed Φ which is content restricted to N we may infer T(Φ)=N[DΦ] via Introduction (Lemma B.2).

( ) Assume T(Φ)=N[DΦ] . By assumption we have ND . Enter this N context. As T(Φ) is content restricted to N we may import it. By Elimination (Lemma B.3) we may infer DΦ and hence Φ .

Leaving this Inner Diamond context gives us NΦ . As Φ content restricted to N we may conclude Φ by Elimination (Axiom 8.2). ■

This fact shows that our translation T(ϕ) of a platonistic theory ϕ implies the same nominalistic sentences observation sentences as the original theory does when combined with the Platonist’s assumption that D (on the plausible assumption that all observation sentences are nominalistic, i.e., content restricted to nominalistic vocabulary). For in this case, we have T(ϕ)ψ iff T(ϕ)T(ϕ) by Theorem D.2 iff (Dϕ)ψ by Theorem D.1. So, our translation of a platonistic scientific theory ϕ implies a nominalistic consequence iff ϕ itself implies ψ given the platonist’s assumptions D about relevant mathematical objects existing.

1 It’s not entirely clear that the Closure Under Multiples requirement requires that space is infinite in extent. For instance, if space is (as some models of General Relativity would suggest) closed back on itself (i.e., has the geometry of the surface of a four-dimensional sphere) then sufficiently long paths would simply start wrapping around the universe. Assuming one is willing to accept such paths then it is much more plausible that something like these conditions hold necessarily (not an assumption we must vindicate but see below) as one might think space can’t have an edge.

2 The fact that y2 is twice the length of x can be expressed as L(x,x,y) , the fact that y3 is three times the length of x can be expressed as the conjunction of the claim that y2 is twice the length of x and L(x,y2,y3) . The closure condition simply asserts the existence of yi for each y (note that while this is a schema, we can replace this with a single formula expressing the same condition in the language of logical possibility by using a categorical description of the natural numbers and turning this into a statement about this logically possible structure).

3 Formally, any time the length of a path a is less than the length of a path b there are paths ci,1in with length i times that of a and cn is longer than b . Again, logical possibility allows us to formalize this schema with an equivalent single sentence.

4 For instance L is transitive, reflexive, etc. and L(p1,p2,p3)L(p2,p1,p3) , etc.

5 Formally, anytime the length of a path a is less than the length of a path b there are paths ci,1in with length i times that of a and cn is longer than b . Again, logical possibility allows us to formalize this schema with an equivalent single sentence.

6 For instance L is transitive, reflexive, etc. and L(p1,p2,p3)L(p2,p1,p3) , etc.

7 Recall that D says there are (objects with the structure of) numbers and functions from spatial paths to numbers and some functions.

Footnotes

1 See Definition E.2 in Section E of the online appendix for formal definition.

1 Before beginning, let me note a technical point about how I will talk about lemmas. Consider the trivial lemma whose content is (∃x)R(x) → (∃x)R(x) . We don’t regard the proof of this lemma as merely establishing the fact that for some particular relation, e.g., redness, if there is some red thing then there is some red thing. Rather, we regard the lemma as standing in for the fact that this result is provable for any one-place relation or, alternately, as proving that the claim in the lemma is logically necessary.

Indeed, we will see shortly if we can prove (∃x)R(x) → (∃x)R(x) without any premises we can infer □[(∃x)R(x) → (∃x)R(x)] and then (as we will also see below) substitute the relations under the and then eliminate it.

Thus, we allow deducing the fact that (∃x)G(x) → (∃x)G(x) from the trivial lemma asserting that (∃x)R(x) → (∃x)R(x) . This resembles the situation in first-order logic where we prove that substitution of bound variables preserves truth-value, and then don’t pay much attention to the particular bound variables used to express results.

2 To this end we treat the initial line in each context and every line introduced via importing (see below) as if they were assumptions inside that context. However, we mark these assumptions with an asterisk since they are justified assumptions (it’s safe to assume they are true in the context) and must be replaced with the line numbers from the parent context when we leave the context.

In accordance with this idea, a sentence ρ can be written down inside the “ ◊ℒ context” governed by the claim that ◊ℒ , iff:

  • ρ=Θ

  • ρ=Ψ for some Γ which is content-restricted to and occurs on an earlier line in the proof which is in the same context as the ◊ℒΘ statement used to introduce this Inner Diamond context. (I will, as usual, sometimes elide the steps needed to transform implicitly content-restricted sentences into first-order logically equivalent explicitly content-restricted sentences.)

  • ρ follows from previous lines within this context by one of the axioms or inference rules for reasoning about logical possibility presented in this book.

3 Note that In E may not be applied to any line with uncancelled (unstarred) assumptions introduced in the context being closed. Moreover, In E must take each starred line number j* on the line on which Φ appears (here that’s line 3 and Φ is (∃x)(cat(x)∨hunter(x)) ) and replace it with the assumptions of the line (in the current context) used to justify line j . For instance, in the current case the only (starred) assumption for line 3 is line 2. Looking at line 2 we see that it is justified by reference to line 1 (which is in the current context). So we copy the line numbers in brackets on line 1 into the brackets on line 4 (in this case that’s just 1).

4 Note that the sentence on line 2 “There are at least three cats” is content-restricted to {cats} (assuming that this abbreviates an FOL statement in the usual Fregian fashion). This fact allows us to import it into our reasoning about what the possible scenario where each cat slept on a different blanket must be like on line 4.

Also note that on line 5 we have proved “there are at least three blankets” with only assumptions [3*,4*] (which are starred because they were introduced by Inner Diamond introduction or importing). Thus, we have shown that the conclusion that there are at least three cats follows from things we are entitled to assume about any logically possible scenario witnessing the truth of the sentence on line 1. So we can apply In Elimination to complete our Inner Diamond argument, and conclude that ◊cat (There are at least three blankets).

Finally, note that the assumption line numbers listed for our conclusion are [1,2] . For these are the assumptions needed for the claims about the actual world (namely the sentences on lines 1 and 2), which entitle us to assume that the possible scenario considered on lines 3–5 satisfy the assumptions on lines 3 and 4 , which imply there are more than three blankets.

See Appendix G in the online appendix for an explicit formal statement of this natural deduction system, and a demonstration that proofs in it obey the notion of provability above.

1 For instance, numbers if formalized in an arithmetic meta-language.

2 That is, if substituting v with v′ does not lead to any variable which was antecedently free becoming bound. Here θ(v|v′) stands for the result of substituting all free instances of v in θ with instances of v′ .

3 Note that Hellman proves something analogous to this lemma in Reference HellmanHellman (1996), assuming there are infinitely many inaccessibles (but I make no such assumption).

4 Strictly speaking we only need to import the finitely many γ∈Γ used to prove ∀vϕ .

5 Intuitively, given any D that is a categorical description of P over N it should be possible to find a D' that imposes the same restrictions but is content-restricted to P∪​N . However, it is not clear how to go about proving this.

1 It’s not entirely clear that the Closure Under Multiples requirement requires that space is infinite in extent. For instance, if space is (as some models of General Relativity would suggest) closed back on itself (i.e., has the geometry of the surface of a four-dimensional sphere) then sufficiently long paths would simply start wrapping around the universe. Assuming one is willing to accept such paths then it is much more plausible that something like these conditions hold necessarily (not an assumption we must vindicate but see below) as one might think space can’t have an edge.

2 The fact that y2 is twice the length of x can be expressed as ⊕L(x,x,y) , the fact that y3 is three times the length of x can be expressed as the conjunction of the claim that y2 is twice the length of x and ⊕L(x,y2,y3) . The closure condition simply asserts the existence of yi for each y (note that while this is a schema, we can replace this with a single formula expressing the same condition in the language of logical possibility by using a categorical description of the natural numbers and turning this into a statement about this logically possible structure).

3 Formally, any time the length of a path a is less than the length of a path b there are paths ci,1≤i≤n with length i times that of a and cn is longer than b . Again, logical possibility allows us to formalize this schema with an equivalent single sentence.

4 For instance ≤L is transitive, reflexive, etc. and ⊕L(p1,p2,p3)↔⊕L(p2,p1,p3) , etc.

5 Formally, anytime the length of a path a is less than the length of a path b there are paths ci,1≤i≤n with length i times that of a and cn is longer than b . Again, logical possibility allows us to formalize this schema with an equivalent single sentence.

6 For instance ≤L is transitive, reflexive, etc. and ⊕L(p1,p2,p3)↔⊕L(p2,p1,p3) , etc.

7 Recall that D says there are (objects with the structure of) numbers and functions from spatial paths to numbers and some functions.

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the HTML of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.g.sjuku.top is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Appendices
  • Sharon Berry
  • Book: A Logical Foundation for Potentialist Set Theory
  • Online publication: 10 February 2022
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Appendices
  • Sharon Berry
  • Book: A Logical Foundation for Potentialist Set Theory
  • Online publication: 10 February 2022
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Appendices
  • Sharon Berry
  • Book: A Logical Foundation for Potentialist Set Theory
  • Online publication: 10 February 2022
Available formats
×